Tuesday, August 11, 2015

Marriage Equality in Australia the Next Steps

"The next step, quite frankly, is having three people or four people that love each other being able to enter into a permanent union endorsed by society …There are even some creepy people out there... [who] say it is OK to have consensual sexual relations between humans and animals. Will that be a future step? In the future will we say, ‘These two creatures love each other and maybe they should be able to be joined in a union? I think that these things are the next step.”

-Senator Cory Bernardi, Australian Senate Debate, 18.09. 12

"I agree with that Senator Sanatorium, if we let this thing go too far, pretty soon, we'll be fucking dogs"
-Tony Soprano, Series 6, Episode 6

Whilst love itself cannot be legislated, the institutional bond of marriage is designed to encourage its longevity and concerns the symbolism of union as much as the procedural comingling of rights and property: if not, why go to an altar or registry surrounded by friends and family and utter ritualistic phrases when one could just send a letter to their solicitor?

This paper aims to demonstrate that whilst tradition and law define marriage as between a male and a female, equality dictates that all natural persons not directly related by blood, who wish to wed (and only non-minors and in non-plural marriages) should, without further limitations, be able to do so using international standards of anti-discrimination justice as the yardstick. A reconsideration of the international terms of reference might be a means for same-sex marriage to occur in the absence of an Act of Australian parliament. This paper will (1) begin with a statutory definition of marriage and review of relevant Australian jurisprudence and (2) assess the current legal position of entitlement to marriage against the backdrop of The Commonwealth v Australian Capital Territory (2013)[1] (the ACT case).

The second part of the paper responds to the notion of (3) limitations and restrictions and finally (4) compares the Australian and international positions before weighing the question of limitations if marriage were to be defined by different parameters to those of The Marriage Act 1961 (Cth) (the Marriage Act). The Constitution cannot in modern times be interpreted to have intended a fundament schism between the symbolic rights of two classes of Australian society.


1. Marriage in Australia
The Constitution confers power on the federal government to make laws pertaining to ‘marriage’ through its own head of power under s. 51 (xxi).  Section 5 of the Marriage Act defines it as “the union of a man and a woman to the exclusion of all others, voluntarily entered into for life”. This stops short of the famous 19th century judicial definition of Lord Penzance (a divorce judge) in Hyde v Hyde and Woodmansee (1866) who defined it thus in Christendom. Whilst marriage is not a Christian institution in Australia[2], or a specifically religious one, the male/female component has been hitherto immutable. It is worth noting that a great deal of the opposition to same-sex marriage is motivated by conservative religious lobbies on both sides of politics. The Shop, Distributive and Allied Employees Association, for instance, the conservative (and originally catholic) Union in the influential right-wing faction of the NSW Branch of the Australian Labor Party does not support marriage equality and along with other conservative Unions within that party will not allow a binding vote in favour of marriage equality. When at the December, 2012 National Conference the party finally granted a conscience vote to its members on the issue of same-sex marriage it was nonetheless a foregone conclusion that a policy resolution in favor an amendment of the Marriage Act would fail under Labor. The then opposition, led by socially conservative (and publicly, staunchly Jesuit) Tony Abbott was also unlikely to change the Act and indeed had a binding vote against doing so, which in government it maintains. For all intents and purposes the state of Australian politics as it stands leaves the matter in perpetual limbo. Nonetheless whilst politics seems paralised on the issue, as Meagher notes, (before the ACT Case) there had been speculative judicial obiter about the breadth of the definition of ‘marriage’ however the constitutional validity to change the definition in terms of gender in The Marriage Act had not been questioned or decided.[3] Meagher’s 2003 exploration into the possibility of whether the act could even validly legislate for same sex marriage considered the obiter of McHugh J in Re Wakim; Ex Parte McNally (1999)[4] which queried whether: “arguably ‘marriage’ now means, or in the near future may mean, a voluntary union for life between two people to the exclusion of others”[5].
The weighing of the connotations of ‘marriage’ between 1900 and today is curious: certainly there is a factual argument that reasons marriage around the world now includes same-sex union, however it is submitted that the mechanics and balance of Australian democratic politics as outlined above shows that the majority of party members (within their party units) of both major parties support the notion that marriage is between a man and a woman and that being the case, determines from a democratic point of view, that regarding the terms of reference of these times, the definition can have no other conclusion than the status quo. That position however is irrelevant to the thesis of this paper which submits that the right for same sex couples to marry is now an internationally accepted one.

2. The ACT Case
The ACT government passed the Marriage Equality (Same Sex) Act 2013 (ACT)(the ACT Act) in October 2013. In so doing the territory advanced the proposition that the Federal Marriage Act did not in fact govern same-sex marriage, which might be articulated as a different species of marriage to traditional heterosexual marriage: to “provide for marriage equality for same sex couples, not for some form of legally recognized relationship which is relevantly different from the relationship of marriage which the federal laws provide for and recognise”, per French CJ, Hayne, Crennan, Kieffel, Bell and Keane JJ at <3>. There is no doubt that the legal fiction that same sex marriage is a different entity to traditional doesn’t sit well with Australian law. Firstly, the parliament considered and defeated two 2012 bills to change the act to solemnise same-sex unions, furthermore s. 3 of the Marriage Amendment Act 2004 (Cth) made clear that (with the insertion of the following to s. 5): “’marriage’ means the union of a man and a woman to the exclusion of all others, voluntarily entered into for life”, whilst s. 88EA of The Marriage Act since that amendment, expressly states that same sex unions solemnised abroad are not, under the act to be deemed Australian marriage.[6] So the question the High Court took upon itself to answer was whether the Federal Government, under s. 51 (xxi) could constitutionally enact laws relating to same sex marriage, and answered this in the affirmative. This being so, the ACT Act was inconsistent with the Marriage Act. The scope of what might Constitutionally constitute marriage was decided at par. 33 to require:
(i)            a consensual union
(ii)         between natural persons (a number of persons omitted)
(iii)      in accordance with legally prescribed requirements
and defined it as:
(iv)       a union recognised by the law,
(v)          intended to endure, terminable only by the law and which
(vi)       affects mutual rights and obligations.
But if the above shows that the High Court interprets that s. 51 (xxi) thus confers federal power to create laws relating to same sex marriage, and that s. 5 of The Marriage Act excludes same sex marriage, surely it follows that the Federal government has the power to either re-amend The Marriage Act or enact a same sex marriage act. If it is enabled to do the latter, then the States and Territories must have the power, in the absence of such an act, to make their own. At paragraphs 56-59, the unanimous judgment seems to reject this argument articulating at par. 59, “the implicit negative proposition that the kind of marriage provided for by the Act is the only kind of marriage that may be formed or recognised in Australia.” But, par. 56 speaks of “the absence of a provision permitting same sex marriage” and not the absence of an act. Herein lies some circular inconsistency within the judgment. There was the further issue under the ACT Act that lacked clarity in whether a man married to another man in the territory, might be able to marry a woman under the federal marriage act.  If one adopts the apples and oranges approach, that the two types of union are distinct, then theoretically one would have two valid unions, but for s. 33 of the ACT Act, the preponderance of these diverse marriage types simplifies the notion that the Constitution can only have envisaged one form of marriage, especially owing to the fact that the framers included s. 51 (xxi) to alleviate complications inherent in the 19th century operation of marriage across the United States of America[7] (though this does not go to why, prior to 1961 Marriage law was the domain of the states).
Whilst some scholars have found the above broad scope (at par. 33 of the judgement) ‘especially problematic’[8] it is submitted that it is a definition that sits with the requirements of modern times.

3. Limitations and Restrictions
Does the potential scope of the Constitutional power under s. 51 (xxi) really cover: forced marriages, marriages amongst minors, incestuous or polygamous marriages or marriages between humans and animals, or even amongst the beasts themselves?
Beginning with animals; that is not what husbandry means! It is a nonsense to suggest that there is any scope allowed for bestial marriage for it only allows for natural persons.
The question of polygamy is open-ended, for the judgment decided that Australian Law does recognise polygamous marriage, indeed the Family Law Act 1975 (Cth), s. 6 recognises a polygamous marriage solemnised in a jurisdiction in which it is or was legal. In the face of s. 88EA of the Marriage Act, it appears that polygamous marriage falls into the scope of what the Federal Parliament could legislate with respect of marriage both under statute and within the jurisprudence. Whether this should be so is open for debate; western polygamy traditionally relates to the popular notion that Mormonism, a branch of the Christian faith in the United States of America permits it (it no longer does). Indeed the case of Hyde v Hyde concerned an English Mormon suing for divorce of a wife. It is curious that the accepted legal definition of Australian marriage under s. 5 of the Marriage Act is based on the judgment of a 19th century British case concerning a former Mormon priest. Whilst in no state in North America is polygamy currently legal, it is in many nations and cultures around the world, that being so and there existing no inherent imbalance in power or influence in choosing to undertake such a marriage, it is submitted that there is no legal basis to state that the federal government does not have the power to legalise polygamy, (especially when under s. 94 of the Marriage Act it prohibits polygamy, in the same reasoning as in the Act Case, it must thereby have the power to allow it). Whether it should is a matter of moral and not legal determination.
Turning to incestuous marriages, the prohibitions in s. 23B of The Marriage Act already exist to exclude such matters, the fear that the broad definitional scope now determines that the Federal parliament could legislate for inter-familial marriage is moot; it already had that power. Whilst marriageable age will be dealt with below, one question that has not been clarified is whether the judgment alludes to the fact that the Federal Government has the power to enact laws relating to customary marriage in the Australian indigenous context. An analogous instance was alluded to in the 19th century case of Bethell v Hildyard (1888)[9] which saw an African colonial polygamous ‘marriage’ overridden by English law prohibiting polygamy. Without further discourse on that subject it is sufficient to say that if it fulfills the scope of the judgment, then Federal parliament can enact laws as to customary Aboriginal marriage within the marriage power.

4. The International context
Regarding the final questions of the marriageable age and forced marriage, it is simple enough to state that the age under the Marriage Act is 18 years (s. 11), or between 16-18 in exceptional and unusual circumstances, as decided by a judge or magistrate (s. 12) and satisfying the consent provisions (ss. 13-16). One question arises as to whether the federal government would have the power to lower that age limit, and if it did, for instance lowering the marriageable age to 14, would that make problematic the compatibility of state criminal acts that define the legal age of consent for sexual conduct as 16-18, similarly what impact would it have on federal codes purporting to regulate the same field?  Article 23 of the International Covenant on International Civil an Political Rights 1966, (the ICCPR), enabled by
Australian Human Rights Commission Act 1986 (Cth) (without any reservation pertaining to that article) protects the recognition of “The right of men and women of marriageable age to marry and to found a family”. Dealing first with the issue of age, the Human Rights Committee did state that “the Covenant does not establish a specific marriageable age either for men or for women, but that age should be such as to enable each of the intending spouses to give his or her free and full personal consent in a form and under conditions prescribed by law.”[10] Forced or non-consensual arranged marriage is prohibited under s. 23B of the Marriage Act, in addition to this, a non-consensual union is not deemed to be constitutionally envisaged by the Marriage power per the judgment in the ACT Case. It might be argued that the jurisprudence for the consensual aspect of marriage, especially in the ACT Case indicates that consent is the very lowest bar for what the constitution could envisage as marriage.
This paper has submitted that a pursuit of marriage-equality by means of International law might advance the possibility of having Australian law altered through international treaty obligations. As was shown above, Article 23 of the ICCPR describes the “right of men and women... to marry”. It is tempting but erroneous to advance the interpretation that this means men and women or men and men or women and women. In Joslin v New Zealand (2002)[11], the HRC rejected the substance of that submission stating that the article “is the only substantive provision in the Covenant that defines a right by using the term ‘men and women’”[12] rather than other more universal terms. The communication in Joslin v New Zealand is along the lines of how one might make a communication to the HRC on the grounds that s. 5 of the Marriage Act is a violation of international human rights under the ICCPR, though in that instance of course it failed, it is possible but unlikely that in the intervening 13 years the situation may have changed substantially to reconsider the matter.
However, article 26 of the ICCPR provides that “all persons are equal before the law and are entitled without any discrimination to the equal protection of the law”. Any future communication need not actually reference Article 23 as it is not relevant to the issue of same sex marriage. In reference to the response in Joslin, even accepting that s. 23 only applies to marriage between men and women, it simply needs to be stated that if a state party has enacted a law that is in violation of Article 26, it need not matter that Article 23 may be referenced (but need not be).

This above is a tidy notion, however everything turns on what constitutes ‘discrimination’. The prevailing notion in Australia is that there is no discrimination between same sex couples and legally married couples at law with regard to their legal and property rights. This is a convenient state of affairs that ignores the practical reality that marriage is about symbolism.
From the ring worn as a symbol of the union, to the ritualistic nature of ‘traditional’ marriage, to the many provisions within the act relating to who may marry two individuals, what the celebrant may say and how; symbolism is inherent in the whole of the activity, which is governed by s. 51 (xxi) of the Constitution. A marriage certificate is not merely another conveyancing document, nor a bill of transfer of chattel ownership. It is more than a recognition of legal obligations: it is a recognition of a union. If the intrinsic symbolic importance is acknowledged by the Marriage Act, then to deny it to citizens based on their sexual orientation is to breach Article 26 of the ICCPR. Following this logic a Tasmanian Dams approach can be pursued however, that level of extension is not in issue. 


Evan Hughes


[1] 250 CLR 441
[2] Attorney-General (Commonwealth) v ‘Kevin and Jennifer’ and Human Rights and Equal Opportunity Commission (2003) 30 Fam LR 1
[3] Dan Meagher, ‘The times are they a-changin’? — Can the Commonwealth parliament legislate for same sex marriages?’ (2003) 17 Australian Journal of Family Law 134
[4] 198 CLR 511
[5] Ibid at <533>
[6] See: The Commonwealth v Australian Capital Territory (2013) 198 CLR 511 at par. 57
[7] Official Record of the Debates of the Australasian Federal Convention, (Sydney), 22 September 1897 at 1080, cited at par 7 of The Commonwealth v Australian Capital Territory (2013) 198 CLR 511
[8] P Parkinson and N Aroney, “The Territory of Marriage: Constitutional Law, Marriage Law and Family Policy in the ACT Same Sex Marriage Case” (2014) 28 Australian Journal of Family Law 160, 185
[9] 38 Ch D 220
[10] General Comment No. 19, Human Rights Committee, 39th Session, Adopted 27 July, 1990, par. 4
[11] HRC 902/1999
[12] Ibit at par. 8.2

Tuesday, April 29, 2014

Roger Brown Iconic/Ironic

Roger Brown was one of the leading painters amongst a group of artists whom we have come to know as the ‘Chicago Imagists’. Art history likes –isms and –ists because its students are more comfortable with compartmentalising species rather than comparing the divergent characteristics of individuals. From many of the various readings, it seems the artists of this period in Chicago were uncomfortable with a strict collective definition but it has stuck and it does no harm; a little like ‘outsider art’; a concept which is globally fashionable but which also doesn’t need any more description than what it is: simply ‘art’. When artists are friends, exhibit together and make complementary works, it can oftentimes give the impression of a shared movement of artistic intent, rather than a common source to each individual’s imagery. Sometimes it is simply a very talented group of individuals who have been lumped together by chance, fashion or convention.
 
Roger Brown in his studio. Courtesy of the Roger Brown Study Collection. Visit the website here

Brown was a regular member of joint-exhibitions and surveys whose thrust and often even names perpetuated a group vibe. Whether Brown and his colleagues were part of a group or not is not of primary importance today; many of the artists are important in their own right and have recently been enjoying surveys and important solo shows. Ultimately, the artists of Chicago from 1966 to now were and are artists with highly individual energies. Their geographical proximity and shared rejection of the prevailing trends in American art at the time bound them more than anything else except perhaps a sense of fun and respect for the supremacy of surface and image over concept.

Nonetheless, Roger Brown was and remains one of the most individual voices in American painting. Despite this statement, he was an artist whose imagery benefited from many sources. Identifying these has become as much fun for art historians and students as quoting them clearly was for the artist in the studio. Whilst it is enjoyable (though exhausting) to pick where Brown’s individual works may have drawn from Georgia O’Keeffe, Arthur Dove, Sienese painting, the work of Joseph Yoakum, Giorgio De Chirico, primitive sculpture, southern folk art, etc. etc, it is his political and social commentary as much as his pictorial ingenuity that commands attention and which is the loose focus of the present exhibition.

Roger Brown died before his time in 1997, and whilst other artists from the period have enjoyed careers that have, along with their lives, endured, Brown’s politics within the work has at times existed in a conservative climate. Many paintings in the oeuvre of Roger Brown explore the politics of sexuality, homosexuality and the cultural stigma that was attached to the AIDS virus, which ultimately claimed his life, in America in the 1980s and 1990s.
To find a path towards the discussion of Brown’s sexual politics, it is important to traverse his visual landscape. Here, an assessment of the skyscraper works will serve as a backdrop for commentary on some of the contentious aspects of his practice.

To know what a Roger Brown painting looks like is to be expected of someone familiar with the work of the ‘Imagists’. Brown’s Land of Lincoln (1978) adorned the jacket cover of Who Chicago? the accompanying publication to the important exhibition of the same name that toured England in 1981. This is perhaps the most important contemporary book that banded and branded the ‘Imagists’. As for his imagery throughout a career, Brown is a good deal more than a painter of tall buildings, although these have been the works often chosen to illustrate him in surveys or articles, are the most sought after commercially and have become the regular mental images of what his work ‘is’ or ‘looks like’ over the years.

Brown possessed an accomplished and distinctive style. He enjoyed a command over composition that allowed for the successful execution of large canvasses with uncomplicated motifs, oftentimes repeating them with a rhythmic nature that was never monotonous. For instance, there is a musical quality to a work such as Buttermilk Sky (1974) with its repeating hills, shrubs and clouds that is kept lively by its various punctuations; a rearing horse, a campervan, a hitchhiker. A similar detail in Virtual Still Life # 22, the airplane is another of  these punctuations but this time an intended, subtle distraction. Within small offerings such as these, unfurl  narratives that are neither obvious nor meaningless. Thus, curiosity and voyeurism become central to Brown’s narrative. It is rare that the viewer is fully aware of the story behind a work’s image unless it is one attached to fact, as in one of his ‘history paintings’, for instance Assassination Crucifix (1975).

Roger Brown, Virtual Still Life # 22: Service with a Smile, 1996, Private Collection

Voyeurism is inherent in the architectural paintings. It is undeniable that Brown’s most famous works depict buildings. If these are his standout subjects, then their windows populated by stylized silhouettes are an important hallmark of his work. It was visiting the Roger Brown Study Collection in Chicago that I realized one aspect of why I had always taken to his work with joy. As a child, I had played with a vintage Dick Tracy tin squad car. The siren whirred as the wheels moved and on the side, front and rear windows, yellow squares framed the front, side and back depictions of the faces of Dick and the other officers in the car. Getting close up to some of the works in the 2012 exhibition, Roger Brown: This Boy’s Own Story  gave me the first opportunity to see the activities of the figures so often lost in images of the works from books.

The windows of the Hancock Building (1974) depict on one side of the sculpture such innocuous scenes as a group dancing, a man being admonished by a woman and a sole woman waving, whilst the  next side depicts several floors of raucous sexual activity playing out. Compare this to the sculpture in the McClain collection (now in the Madison Museum of Contemporary Art, Wisconsin), Skyscraper Pyramid (1974) and that seems an altogether better behaved address. Then again, in Me’s Building Highrise (1972) an entire lewd liason from anonymous meeting in the park to post-coital smoking seems to play out in a simultaneous depiction for one lucky couple on every floor of a strikingly similar building to the McClain pyramid.

Roger Brown, Hancock Building, 1974, Roger Brown Study Collection,
 the School of the Art Institute of Chicago. Visit the website here
 
Identifying Brown’s regularly appearing characters: the woman with her  hair elaborately coiffed, the young  man with his peaked at the front for example, is not of urgent necessity. If desperate to find identity, the publication Roger Brown: Southern Exposure bears two helpful images that the viewer may use to make up their mind: one is a self-portrait sketch c. 1960 whereby the hair on the youth mirrors that which recurs in the windows on the young figure. A second image depicts a photograph from the mid-1940s of his parents at the beach, where his mother wears her hair very similarly to the recurring woman (usually standing shocked). Neither hairstyle was remarkably rare for the era and reading too much into this, whilst tempting, serves no real purpose. Whilst art is arguably inherently autobiographical, Brown’s was about conveying the mood of the time. These paintings were as much about sexual liberation or repression in general, as about Brown’s own.

Identities and activities of the occupants aside, whether the architecture paintings became synonymous with the style of Brown because they were the strongest compositionally or that they assisted the placement of ‘Imagism’ in geographical terms is unclear. In an essay in the publication Art in Chicago: 1945-1995 prepared for an exhibition of the same name at the Museum of Contemporary Art, Chicago in 1996, Judith Russi Kirshner states “Brown positioned himself in his artwork as an anti-authoritarian outsider” and that he “anthropomorphized the city’s modern skyscrapers and paradoxically became the standard bearer for Chicago Imagism”.  Kirschner also weighs the suggestion put forward by Mary Gedo that the architectural works relate biographically to his “positive alliance” with architect George Veronda, (1940-1984) whom Brown began a relationship with in 1972.

Notwithstanding artistic motive, which likely varied from work to work, the city/building works are laced with wit, much like the modernist and post modernist architecture of the city. An industry flourishes along the river through Chicago with countless amusing but conflicting stories relating to the inspirations behind or architectural theories surrounding the buildings across the city, as told by  the guides on the river cruises that go up and down ad nauseum. Possibly none of the architectural works holds as much inherent humour as Post-Modern Res/Erection with Observation Deck (1984). Attached to this work is the most obvious notion of the attachment of ego to the size of one’s erection, architectural or otherwise. There is nothing subtle about the fact that even though Chicago’s John Hancock Centre is 25 meters taller than the Chrysler Building in New York, it is still 37 meters shorter than The Empire State Building. When ,in 1972, the first World Trade Centre soared at 417 meters it would take until the Sears Tower in Chicago was finally erected in 1974 at 442 meters before people could rest assured of their superiority in Chicago. Little articulation about the phallic connotations and the superiority/inferiority dilemma therein associated is really required. Remember, Hancock Centre was illustrated in Who Chicago as ‘Big John’.

On a somber note, it is worth examining a number of works in a very different light, to put into the literature on his painting an interesting observation that followed his life. Brown, as will be discussed further below, was conscious of social and political events and often depicted them. Dying in 1997, Brown missed the earthmoving events of September 11, 2001, their aftermath and the visuals that the world was met with. One cannot help but consider Twin Towers (1977), the sculpture in the SAIC’s New Buffalo collection against the backdrop of preceding works such as Ablaze and Ajar (1972) in the Museum of Contemporary Art Collection, Tropical Storm (1972) and Midnight Tremor (1972). It is disturbing but difficult not to compare the grim imagery of the falling figures depicted in the canvases, tumbling, arms outstretched from the buildings whilst they crumble and breaks apart, to those photographs that few can forget of the victims falling to their deaths from great height before the twin towers came down. Brown, who never made an image flippantly seems, with a work such as Ablaze and Ajar to be portending something about the march of society, or the pace and peril of modern life. Within this frame, these works lose all their humour and adopt enormous power. Such is the strength of the period’s motif.

Roger Brown, Ablaze and Ajar, 1972, collection of the Museum of Contemporary Art,
Chicago. Visit the website here
 
There is probably little doubt as to the side of politics Brown might have fallen on as dictated by his art alone. The imagery of his political discourse is fairly liberal and the wit with which it is portrayed has the hallmarks of that thoughtful, amusing style of political commentary Australian audiences might associate with the pages of the New Yorker. This is not a strictly speaking ‘Democratic’ viewpoint, but at least a thoughtful one. His outlook might at once loathe most of the politics of Reaganism but adore the charm, bravado and at times self-parodying nature of the Reagans themselves. The present exhibition, His American Icons draws specifically on Presidential Portrait (1986). This work, now in a private collection in Sydney, is a classic piece. It puzzles me that it has hitherto remained unsold in the estate. Included in the 1987 retrospective of Brown’s work at the Hirshhorn Museum and Sculpture Garden, and illustrated on p. 80 of the catalogue, it is one of the great directly political works in his output. It could be advanced that the subject had posed a problem with his otherwise Democratic audiences in liberal Chicago and New York.
The irony so successfully portrayed by an artist who owned a novelty pair of Reagan slippers is the crucial aspect to the work. Irony is a central theme in the political works: Brown was not in the business of jamming tough medicine down the throat of his audience; his was a point that was best delivered with cutting but amusing elegance. Much like a joke at someone’s expense, his political works are laced with enough humour to provoke either hearty amusement or at least nervous laughter, often both when successful. Presidential Portrait does speak about American icons. Politics is polarizing. The simple image of Obama’s Hope campaign from the 2008 election raises both pride and ire depending on the audience. How dearly we might long to see how Brown, the most visually communicative and specific artists of his day might have commented on the characterization of America now: how would Brown record the election of Obama or document the Gifford Assasination attempt or the tragedy of the Sandy Hook Elementary School shooting? One particular event in the United States that Brown should have been able to depict upon his canvas was that important court ruling in 2013 when the US Supreme Court struck down as unconstitutional, the key section of the Defence of Marriage Act (DOMA), passed by the Clinton administration (who would later advocate its repeal) a year before Brown’s death . The most enduring image from this episode was Jack Hunter’s cover of The New Yorker depicting the Sesame Street ‘friends’ Bert and Ernie watching the ruling on their television.

Roger Brown, Presidential Portrait, 1986, Private Collection
 
Writers are careful with the sensitive nature of Brown’s ultimate demise. However, one should be disinclined to remain too politely silent about what invariably, the man who painted Aha! Heterosexuals Fuck Too (1991) clearly wanted debated. Attitudes towards both heterosexual and homosexual victims of HIV and AIDS remain varied. Aha! is a powerful work dealing with how ‘civilized’ America was supposed to deal with the iconic Magic Johnson suffering from the ‘gay’ disease. Stigma has haunted this virus and it continues to do so. More and more education, prevention and better treatment is changing this perception, however it has some way to go. That said, as with the newly unconstitutional nature of DOMA, and more nations legalizing same sex marriages, attitudes are changing; something that Brown had begun discussing many years ago. His works today are important pioneering images at the beginning of that arduous path.

Roger Brown, Aha! Heterosexuals Fuck Too, 1991, Roger Brown Estate
Painting  Collection, the School of the Art Institute of Chicago. Visit the website here
 
Roger Brown painted sharp, idiosyncratic paintings and made sculptures that challenged and played with the conventions of the boundary between fine sculpture, low object and also painting itself. From the earliest canvases in the current show, the theatre images, to the California Gawkers painted in the final year of his life, he advanced his argument about how form could be non-naturalistically but elegantly conveyed on a canvas. There is much to be said about the importance of Roger Brown’s subject matter, and throughout the oeuvre it calls for fun as well as serious considerations. The most powerful of Brown’s works interlace irony with his desired message; they use a playful gesture or narrative to convey his statements.

Roger Brown, California Gawkers, 1997, Roger Brown Study Collection,

he School of the Art Institute of Chicago. Visit the website here



EH

Copyright © Evan E Hughes